Epistemic Justification by Richard Swinburne

(Oxford University Press, 2001, 262 pp.)

 

David Mackie

 

'Justified' is one of a number of closely related terms in epistemology, including 'reasonable', 'rational', and 'warranted'. Epistemologists' concern is with what it takes for a person's belief to be justified. Of course, beliefs are also evaluated for their truth or falsity, and justification is not wholly unrelated to that area of evaluation: we want our beliefs to be true, and typically (at least) the value of epistemic justification is that a belief's being justified makes it more likely to be true. Still, a belief's being true is not the same thing as its being justified: for a person may justifiably believe what is false, and a person may believe what is true but without justification.

 

In the standard debate, two main distinctions are usually made. First, there is the distinction between foundationalists and coherentists: foundationalists hold that epistemic justification has a tiered structure, with some beliefs being 'basic'—that is, standing in no need of support from other beliefs—while other beliefs are justified in virtue of being supported by more basic beliefs. Coherentists, by contrast, deny that any beliefs are basic, and say that beliefs are justified insofar as they form a system of mutually-supporting beliefs. Secondly, there is a distinction between internalists, who hold that what makes for justification is something internal to the believer, and accessible to him by introspection, and externalists, who maintain that what makes for justification are states of affairs that need not be mentally accessible to the believer (typically, this view is that a belief's being justified is a matter of its being produced by a process of the right kind).

 

Swinburne's book is intended mainly as a guide to the various different accounts of epistemic justification that are current in the literature. The book falls naturally into two parts. In chapters 1 to 5, Swinburne leads the reader through the relevant notions that appear in different accounts of epistemic justification. Belief is discussed in chapter 2. Next, since justification of belief is often elucidated in terms of the belief's being probable, chapter 3 offers a detailed account of distinctions between different senses of 'probability', which leads to the conclusion that externalist accounts of the adequacy of grounds for belief will need to be spelled out in terms of 'physical' or 'statistical' probability (and more plausibly only the latter), whereas internalist accounts will need to be spelled out in terms of some form of 'inductive' probability. Chapter 4 then concentrates on one form of inductive probability, which Swinburne calls 'logical probability'. This terms denotes the measure of inductive support that would be reached by a logically omniscient being (one who knew all the relevant logical probabilities, what they entailed, and had correct inductive criteria). Chapter 5 discusses the foundationalist's notion of a basic belief, and more generally the notion of one belief's being based on another. The remaining three chapters build on this material, discussing the value of justification (chapters 6 and 7) and knowledge (chapter 8), which is of course linked to the main subject-matter in that knowledge is supposed to be something of the same kind as, but somehow superior to, justified belief.

 

The main conclusion of the book is that what often purport to be rival theories of epistemic justification are not in fact genuine rivals, at most one of which could be correct, for the title 'the correct account of epistemic justification'. As Swinburne claims, there is no single concept at work here; rather, there is a range of more or less closely related concepts of 'justification', and the different accounts that philosophers have offered are really no more than accounts of various different kinds of justification. That conclusion, even if it is not particularly striking or surprising, is admirably supported by the wealth of detailed and carefully presented distinctions that are provided, especially in the first five chapters. Here there is a huge amount of carefully yet economically presented detail, elucidating the interplay between the mains types of theory of justification and the different understandings of the central concepts of probability, evidence, and 'basing'.

 

But Swinburne also goes further, notably in two additional areas of discussion. For he goes on, in chapters 6 and 7, to give an account of the value of particular kinds of justification. The discussion here includes two important distinctions—the distinction between synchronic justification (justification that a belief has at a time) and diachronic justification (justification resulting from a belief's being based on adequate investigation over a period of time), and (within synchronic justification) between subjective and objective justification. In chapter 8, which is in some ways the most accessible and the most likely to be of immediate use to undergraduates following a typical course in epistemology, Swinburne offers a discussion of knowledge in which, as well as critically analysing certain aspects of various contemporary accounts of knowledge, he explains with considerable plausibility how it is that the different accounts of knowledge largely coincide to a greater degree than do the different accounts of justification.

 

In its intended role as a guide through the main theories of justification, Swinburne's book serves superbly well. I was left with a greatly improved understanding of the complex interplay between different theories and their correspondingly different understandings of the relevant underlying concepts. Swinburne's hope that the main text will be comprehensible by the average undergraduate, however, may be a little optimistic. Although it is true that Swinburne has consigned a lot of the finer and more technical points to an Appendix and a series of Additional Notes, quite a lot of fairly difficult material remains in the main text (and the probability that most of the students I have taught would simply despair when confronted with the formula on p. 161, for example, must be, if not actually 1, quite close to it).

 

In this context, it is a slight pity that Swinburne's generally very clear exposition is sometimes marred by the kind of infelicities that a firmer editorial hand might have eliminated. In addition to a number of trivial typographical errors, there is the odd howler ("But if you take a bit wider region…" (p. 202)), and the following incomprehensible sentence on p. 140, which delayed me for several minutes: "Now, it is plausible to suppose that the very fact of my believing that some proposition being forced upon me by my experience or by the deliverance of reason is as such reason for me to believe it to be true." My most general minor irritation arose from Swinburne's strangely uncertain handling of gerunds (of which there are many in the book), which veers back and forth between treating them as if they were really participles and as nouns (and the usage is, on more than one occasion, inconsistent even within a single sentence (e.g. on pp. 76 & 204)). But these are minor quibbles which do not seriously affect the reader's understanding of what is overall an exceptionally useful, thorough, and interesting guide to the subject.