FISCHER ON ALTERNATIVE POSSIBILITIES AND
RESPONSIBILITY
David Mackie
. . . Black inserts a mechanism into Jones’ brain which enables Black to
monitor and control Jones’ activities. Jones, meanwhile, knows nothing of this.
Black exercises this control through a sophisticated computer which he has
programmed so that, among other things, it monitors Jones’ voting behavior. If
Jones were to show any inclination to vote for Bush, then the computer, through
the mechanism in Jones’ brain, intervenes to assure that he actually decides to
vote for
This
case, presented by John Martin Fischer, is an example of a kind of case devised
originally by Harry Frankfurt and designed to refute an intuitively attractive
thesis about responsibility—the thesis that alternative possibilities are
necessary for moral responsibility.[2]
Following others, I shall call this thesis the Principle of Alternative
Possibilities, or PAP. PAP, of course, is of interest because, if true, it
supports the incompatibility of causal determinism and responsibility; for
causal determinism would rule out the existence of the alternative
possibilities that (according to PAP) there must be, if attributions of moral
responsibility are to be correct.
Though
the standard argument against PAP that is based on these Frankfurt-type cases
is fairly obviously flawed, Fischer has recently presented an ingenious new
argument, based on the Frankfurt-type cases, which he thinks does present a
genuine threat to PAP. Fischer’s argument is among the more interesting recent
contributions to the continuing debate about determinism and responsibility. It
is this new argument that I want to examine in this paper. First, however, it will
be helpful to consider briefly the standard version of the argument.
I
The
standard version of the argument against PAP that is based on cases of this
kind runs as follows. Suppose that Jones decides to vote for
This
Standard Argument runs, in effect, as follows:
(1) In the Jones and Black case as described, Jones is responsible for
acting as he does.
But
(2) Jones has no alternative to acting as he does.
Therefore
(3) PAP is incorrect.
As
Fischer is aware, however, there is a simple and obvious reply to this standard
argument. The reply can be stated as follows:[3]
Initial
impressions notwithstanding, the Frankfurt-type cases do involve alternative possibilities. In other words, premiss (2)
in the argument is straightforwardly false. All such cases must involve both an
actual sequence and a counterfactual one, and these sequences will be genuine
alternatives to one another. In our case of Jones and Black, the actual
sequence is the one in which Jones decides on his own to vote for Clinton and
does so; the counterfactual sequence is the one in which he sets out (whatever,
precisely, such ‘setting out’ involves) to vote for Bush, but the computer
intervenes to ensure that he votes for Clinton. Defenders of PAP can simply
point out that, in imagining the case, we assume that Jones does have the power
to choose between these two sequences—we assume that, though he actually
decides to vote for
Now, since
Jones ends up voting for
The
crucial point is that defenders of PAP can correctly point out that the Jones
and Black case does involve an alternative possibility. Hence the standard
argument does not succeed in its attempt to provide a counterexample to PAP—a
case of responsibility in the absence of an alternative possibility. Since this
is so, and as Fischer rightly concludes, the standard argument that is based on
the Frankfurt-type cases fails to establish the falsity of PAP.
II
I turn
now to consideration of Fischer’s new argument against PAP. Fischer’s
suggestion is that, although the Frankfurt-type cases involve alternative
possibilities, these possibilities are ‘not sufficiently robust’ to ground the
relevant attributions of responsibility. Though there is an alternative
possibility in the Jones and Black case, it is, according to Fischer, ‘highly
implausible to suppose that it is in
virtue of the existence of such an alternative possibility that Jones is
morally responsible for what he does.’ According to Fischer, it is not enough
for the defender of PAP to show that these cases involve alternative
possibilities; ‘what also needs to be shown is that these alternative
possibilities play a certain role in
the appropriate understanding of the cases. That is, it needs to be shown that
these alternative possibilities ground our attributions of moral
responsibility.’[5] But
that, he says, cannot be shown; for the alternative possibilities in these
cases are not sufficiently robust. What makes them insufficiently robust is
that they are possibilities in which the agent ‘does not act freely’.
Briefly think about the basic
picture of control that underlies [PAP] . . . Here the future is a garden of
forking paths. At various points in life, it is envisaged that there are
various paths that branch into the future, and one can determine which of these
genuinely open pathways becomes the actual path of the future. The existence of
various genuinely open pathways is
alleged to be crucial to the idea
that one has control of the relevant
kind. But if this is so, I suggest that it would be very puzzling and unnatural
to suppose that it is the existence of various alternative pathways along which
one does not act freely that shows
that one has control of the kind in question. . . . And notice that this is
precisely the situation in the Frankfurt-type cases. In particular, note that .
. . it is . . . evident that Jones would not be freely voting for
Fischer’s
central idea is that, although the Frankfurt-type cases are not straightforward
counterexamples to PAP, they can be used to challenge PAP in an indirect way.
For if the alternative possibilities in these cases are insufficiently robust
to ground the attributions of responsibility in the actual sequences, they are
not doing the work that defenders of PAP must claim that they do. If so, that
casts doubt on the view that these alternative possibilities are necessary for
responsibility at all.
This
new argument may be recast as follows:
(1) In the Jones and Black case as described, Jones is responsible for
acting as he does.
(2) In the counterfactual sequence, in which Jones sets out to vote for
Bush but Black’s device intervenes, Jones’s action is unfree.
(3) If action in a counterfactual sequence is unfree, then the existence
of this alternative sequence cannot be part of the reason why the agent is
responsible for what (s)he actually does.
Therefore
(4) The existence of this counterfactual sequence is irrelevant to
Jones’s being morally responsible for acting as he does.
Hence, plausibly,
(5) PAP is incorrect.
III
Clearly,
the interesting new premisses here are (2) and (3). We can begin by considering
premiss (2). Fischer’s new argument depends on the description of the Jones’s
action in the alternative sequence as ‘unfree’. Accordingly, to assess his
suggestion, we need to understand what this means. Curiously, Fischer himself
nowhere explains in any detail what the term is supposed to mean in this context.
Particularly in a work on free will, such cavalier use of this term is, to say
the least, unfortunate. Still, it is fairly clear what the point must be:
Jones’s action in the alternative sequence is presumably unfree in that it is
Black’s computer that controls Jones’s behaviour here. Once the computer
intervenes, Jones’s choices and actions are unfree in that it is not up to him
what he does: the computer controls what he does; it causes him to decide to
vote for
We can
agree, then, that Jones’s action in the counterfactual sequence is, in this
sense of the term, unfree. Hence premiss (2) in Fischer’s argument, understood
in this way, is unobjectionable. Premiss (3), however, is much more dubious:
Jones’s action in the counterfactual sequence is unfree. But it is very
doubtful whether this has the intuitive significance that Fischer claims it
has. For it remains entirely unclear why this fact should render it implausible
that the existence of this alternative sequence can ground the ascription of
responsibility in the actual sequence. What Jones does in the counterfactual
sequence is caused and controlled by Black’s computer. But that does not alter
the fact that, in the case as we have imagined it, Jones has the ability, or
freedom, to choose which of the two sequences occurs: he is imagined to have
the ability to choose whether to vote for
Fischer
is right that, if PAP is correct, there must be some feature of the Jones and Black case that renders the
counterfactual sequence capable of grounding the attribution of responsibility
in the actual sequence. The counterfactual sequence must be, to use Fischer’s
terminology, sufficiently ‘robust’. To see why this is so, we need only consider
the obvious truth that the mere presence of some
alternative, counterfactual, possibility is not sufficient for responsibility
in the actual case. Causal determinists, for example, believe that earlier
states of the world, together with the laws of nature, entail later states of
the world. Although I cannot change either the way the world was in the past,
or the laws of nature, these determinists may believe that it is nonetheless
true that I could have done otherwise than I actually did. For they may hold
that I could have done otherwise if the past, or the laws of nature, had been
different. Still, even if there is in this sense an alternative possibility, it
is completely implausible to suppose that the existence of this kind of alternative possibility renders me responsible for
what I actually did. It is insufficiently robust to ground such an attribution
of responsibility. Again:
Fischer
is right, then, that alternative possibilities must have some property of
robustness, if they are to ground ascriptions of responsibility for what an
agent actually does. Moreover, he is right in thinking that robustness depends
on the agent’s having a certain kind of freedom. But he locates this freedom incorrectly, and in so doing misrepresents our
intuitions, when he assumes without argument that the relevant freedom would
have to be freedom (in the sense specified) of action in the counterfactual sequence. Fischer assumes that
robustness, for defenders of PAP, would have to be an intrinsic property of the
action that takes place in the counterfactual sequence: he assumes that it
would have to be a matter of such action’s being ‘free’, where its being ‘free’
entails, at least, that it is not caused and controlled in the way that Jones’s
action is controlled by Black’s computer. But this view is implausible.
Robustness is far more plausibly to be identified with a relational property of
the counterfactual sequence itself: a counterfactual sequence is robust only if
the agent had the ability, or freedom, to choose the occurrence of that
sequence, rather than the actual one.
After
all, in the examples given above, the lack of robustness is clearly not due to the fact that the agents in
the counterfactual sequences do not act freely (in the sense specified).
Rather, what is wrong is simply that these agents do not have the ability, or
freedom, to choose which of the two possible sequences is actual: I do not have
the freedom to choose the laws of nature or to alter the past; England’s
cricketers do not have the freedom to choose to be more naturally talented than
they actually are. It is, then, far more plausible to suppose that it is this kind of freedom that is relevant to
the robustness of an alternative possibility. Indeed, it is hard to see how
freedom of action in the counterfactual sequence could be relevant: after all, how could a freedom that is never exercised conceivably be relevant
to whether an agent is responsible for what he actually does? Far more
plausibly, what matters here is the freedom that is exercised—the freedom, which precedes
the counterfactual sequence itself, to choose which of the two possible
sequences occurs. This view of robustness provides the most plausible
explanation of the truth of PAP: alternative possibilities are necessary for
responsibility not because of any intrinsic property of what happens in these
counterfactual sequences, but simply because the existence of such sequences is
essential to the agent’s having a choice to make: an agent cannot have the
relevant freedom to choose unless there are alternatives for him to choose
between. And, on this more plausible view, the alternative possibilities in the
Frankfurt-type cases are robust.
Defenders of PAP, then, can reply to Fischer’s argument by rejecting premiss
(3) in the formulation given above.
IV
Once we
recognise that robustness does not depend on there being any free (in the sense
specified) action in the
counterfactual sequence itself (after, that is, this sequence has been
initiated), but depends, rather, on the agent’s having the freedom, or ability,
to choose whether that sequence occurs, we can also see the weakness in an
appeal that Fischer makes to an epistemological analogy in support of his view.
Fischer writes:
. . . certain accounts of knowledge imply that an agent knows that p only if he can distinguish a class of
situations in which p obtains from a
contrasting class in which p does not
obtain. On this approach, knowledge requires a certain kind of discriminatory capacity; this model is
clearly analogous with the view that moral responsibility requires regulative
control [i.e., the kind of control that implies the presence of alternative
possibilities]. More specifically, on this approach to knowledge, an agent
knows that p only if there exists a
set of alternatives to the actual world in which the agent’s beliefs line up
with states of the world in the right way. What would be highly implausible
would be to suppose that what transforms some case of lack of knowledge into a
case of knowledge would be the existence of a range of alternative scenarios in
which the agent gets it wrong! . . .
[A]rguably, it is not much more plausible to suggest that it is in virtue of a
set of alternative possibilities in which Jones does not act freely that he actually can be held morally responsible for
his behavior.[7]
Fischer’s
use of this analogy would be unobjectionable if it were the case that
responsibility in the actual sequence depended on the presence of free (in the
sense specified) action in the counterfactual sequence. That would be true, if
robustness required freedom of action in
the counterfactual sequence itself—after
that sequence is under way. If this were the case, then freedom of action in the counterfactual sequence would indeed play
a role in responsibility that was analogous to the role that truth of belief in the alternative scenarios
plays in knowledge (according to this kind of account of knowledge). But that
account of robustness, as I have already argued, is implausible and
counterintuitive. Rather, what is relevant is whether the agent has the freedom
to decide which sequence becomes actual. The exercise of this freedom clearly precedes
the chosen sequence. Since this is so, the relevance of alternative
possibilities to moral responsibility is not analogous to the relevance of
alternative scenarios to knowledge, on the kind of account of knowledge to
which Fischer refers. Since the cases are in this way non-analogous, Fischer’s
appeal to this epistemological example does nothing to support his argument
against PAP.
V
Though
more thoroughly worked out, the response to Fischer’s argument against PAP that
I have given here is similar in essence to an objection that Fischer himself
briefly considers, but rejects. Accordingly, I need finally to examine this
objection and Fischer’s reply to it.
An
opponent, Fischer writes,
. . . may respond that nevertheless there is at least the following
thing in the alternative sequence which is freely done: Jones begins to
initiate the process of making a choice to vote for Bush. (Of course, this
process is then cut off before it can be completed.) So we seem to have
isolated at least something in the
alternative sequence which can plausibly be thought to be freely done and which
thus may be able to ground the ascriptions of responsibility.[8]
Against
this reply, Fischer appeals to a variant of the Jones and Black case in which
what triggers the intervention of the computer is an involuntary sign evinced
by Jones which precedes any initiating action of making a choice, or forming an
intention, or setting out in any other way, to vote for Bush.
Suppose we . . . consider [a] version of the Jones and Black case in
which Black can be alerted to Jones’ future inclination to vote for Bush by the
presence of some involuntary sign, such as a blush or a twitch or even a
complex neurophysiological pattern. So if Jones were (say) to blush red, then
Black would intervene prior to Jones’ doing anything
freely and ensure that Jones indeed votes for
The
argument based on this variant of the Jones and Black case can be summarised as
follows:
(1) In this variant of the case, Jones is responsible for acting as he
does.
(2) What would activate Black’s device is not any decision or action of
Jones’s, but an involuntary blush or twitch.
Therefore
(3) Jones here lacks the ability to choose which sequence occurs.
Therefore
(4) The existence of the counterfactual sequence is irrelevant to
Jones’s being morally responsible for what he actually does.
Hence, plausibly,
(5) PAP is incorrect.
Though
ingenious, this reply is unsuccessful. To start with, the inference from (2) to
(3) here is dubious. It can’t be assumed that because a blush is involuntary,
Jones has no ability to control whether it occurs. Involuntary blushes and
twitches might be under an agent’s control. For example: by deliberately
reflecting on some recent embarrassing experience, I can cause myself to blush
involuntarily; by crossing my legs in a certain fashion, I can ensure that some
involuntary twitching occurs. Moreover, I can (it seems) choose whether to
reflect, or cross my legs, in these ways. If this is how things stand with
Jones, however, then the case is clearly of no use to Fischer. For if Jones has
the ability to choose whether the course of events in which the relevant sign
is evinced takes place, then he plainly does have the ability to choose which
of the two sequences—actual or counterfactual—occurs. But that ability, or freedom, as I have already argued, is precisely
the kind of freedom that can ground the attribution of responsibility that we
make.
For a
case which has some hope of serving Fischer’s purposes, we need to suppose not
merely that the triggering event is involuntary, but that Jones has no ability
to decide whether it occurs. We need to stipulate
that premiss (3) in the argument is true. We must suppose that the triggering
sign would appear when, but only when, Jones was about to set out to vote for
Bush, but before he did anything. And we must suppose that the evincing of this
sign is outside Jones’s control in this sense: he must literally not have the
ability, or freedom, to decide whether or not the course of events in which the
sign is evinced takes place. If this is how things stand, however, then it
clearly follows that Jones literally has no ability, or freedom, to choose
which of the two sequences occurs. But, importantly, where this is so, we will
not, after all, be inclined to hold him responsible for what he actually does:
we will not regard him, in the actual sequence, as an appropriate candidate for
attributions of responsibility. That is, when the case is set up in this way, I
see no reason why we should continue to accept premiss (1). In other words, if
we revise the case in the way that Fischer requires, we do indeed end up with a
case in which, though there are two sequences, the alternative possibility is
insufficiently robust to ground ascriptions of responsibility. But that
presents no threat to PAP; for in revising the case in this way we have
converted it into a case in which it is no longer natural to think that Jones
is an appropriate candidate for attributions of moral responsibility. What
Fischer needs, of course, is a case in which it is intuitively plausible to
hold Jones responsible for what he does in the actual sequence, but in which
the counterfactual sequence is insufficiently robust to ground that attribution
of responsibility. But, despite his efforts, he has simply failed to present
any such case.
[1] J. M. Fischer, The Metaphysics of Free Will (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 131-132.
All subsequent references to Fischer are to this book.
[2] See H. Frankfurt, ‘Alternate
Possibilities and Moral Responsibility’, Journal
of Philosophy 66 (1969), 829-839.
[3] Fischer calls this kind of reply to
the standard argument the ‘Flicker of Freedom strategy’, and he distinguishes
several different ‘versions’ of the strategy (Fischer 134-140). The way I
present the reply here contains elements of Fischer’s first, third, and fourth
versions. But the distinctions between the versions are unimportant for the
purposes of this paper.
[4] Being ignorant of the existence of
Black’s device, Jones does not, of course, know this; but that obviously makes
no difference here.
[5] Fischer 140.
[6] Fischer 140-141.
[7] Fischer 141-142.
[8] Fischer 143-144.
[9] Fischer 144.